ABSTRACT

Please find below an early draft of my paper “Self and Property.”  The central question I will be discussing is: how does the self’s having of the external world correlate with the self’s being its self.  I have already investigated this issue in Levinas, Hegel, and Marx.  I am continuing to work through this problem in Locke and Rousseau, Kant and Fichte, Stirner and Proudhon, and Husserl and Heidegger.  Below is a series of notes and texts I have patched together thus far.  The discussion in the final presentation paper will be balanced differently, and will develop a consistent narrative thread.

            This current draft traces Selfhood, and Property, and the Person:

  1. Locke introduces the “Person” as an internal relationship of Self-Ownership, who can own external Property through Labor.
  2. Rousseau distinguishes between Self-Love and Proper Love, which roughly correlates to the distinction between the individual in a Natural or Social context.  Contra Locke, Rousseau argues that the institution of property does not naturally derive from an internal relationship, but rather is imposed by force in society.
  3. Kant builds off of Locke and Rousseau to more specifically locate the concept of the Person as a natural individual within a social context.  He similarly understands Property through the distinction between natural empirical possession and social rightful ownership. 
  4. Hegel discuses the person as a distinct property-owning class in Roman Law.  He discusses the various ways personality can be alienated legitimately in contract, exchange of goods, labor relationships, and illegitimately in slavery.
  5. Marx traces the way that the person is necessarily alienated in order to produce an objective culture of social use values.  The second-order mediation of private property further alienates the person from her own active personhood into an exploitable wage laborer.
  6. Levinas employs the distinction between the moi (me) and the soi (self) to designate different ways that the person is enacted through being and having.  He describes how the necessary objectification through property disrupts self-identity and makes one responsible for one’s acts of consumption.

I.  LOCKE AS MODERN THEORIST OF THE PERSON AND PROPERTY

In his political and philosophical writings, John Locke articulates the notion of the self as an individual property owner.  His Second Treatise on Government can be understood as a response to two currents of thought, both based on the biblical narrative of Genesis:  legal theorists Grotius and Puffendorf proposed the idea that the earth was originally given to all men in common; Robert Filmer proposed that all ownership derives from God’s original dispensation of the earth to Adam and that property rights and political power follow exclusively and absolutely according to patriarchal descent from Adam. 

            In opposition to this, Locke bases the right to private property in an individual’s self-identity and self-ownership.  “Though the earth and all inferior creatures be common to all men, yet every man has a ‘property’ in his own ‘person.’”  For Locke, all property ownership ultimately originates in the fact that a man is his own, proper person.

            In addition to locating the right to private property in an individual’s self-identity and self-ownership, Locke is generally credited as being the first thinker to propose a labor theory of property.  One’s personhood is not an abstraction, but the concrete materiality of one’s body.  By combining the efforts of one’s own physical body with the objects in the external world, the person can turn these objects into his own personal property.

            The civil State arises from an agreement among persons to mutually respect and protect each other’s individual property.

 

 

ROUSSEAU

            Especially in the Second Discourse on Inequality, Rousseau contests Locke’s image of the person as a property owner. 

            Although individuals are born with inequalities in certain natural or physical properties such as strength and intelligence, this does not automatically justify moral and cultural inequalities in property ownership.

            This distinction seems related to his differentiation between two different kinds of love: “We must not confuse Proper Love [amour proper, typically translated as “self-love”] with love of oneself [amour de soi même], two very different passions in their natures and their effects. Love of oneself is a natural feeling which inclines every animal to watch out for its own preservation and which, directed in man by reason and modified by pity, produces humanity and virtue. Proper-love [amour propre] is only a relative feeling, something artificial and born in society, which inclines each individual to think of himself as more important than all the others, which inspires in men all the evils they do to each other, and which is the true source of honour.”

            Proper love thus arises out of a competition between actors in the sociopolitical realm.  Whereas each person in a state of nature is his own master, the civic mutual dependences creates bonds of servitude.  Thus Rousseau claims “it is impossible to make any man a slave, unless he be first reduced to a situation in which he cannot do without the help of others.”

            Rousseau argues in the Second Discourse that property ownership arises not from individual personhood but rather from social coercion:

THE first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, bethought himself of saying This is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him, was the real founder of civil society. …  The idea of property depends on many prior ideas, which could only be acquired successively, and cannot have been formed all at once in the human mind.

      

 

KANT

From Metaphysic of Morals:

Persons:

(1)    A person is a subject who is capable of having his actions imputed to him. Moral personality is, therefore, nothing but the freedom of a rational being under moral laws; and it is to be distinguished from psychological freedom as the mere faculty by which we become conscious of ourselves in different states of the identity of our existence. Hence it follows that a person is properly subject to no other laws than those he lays down for himself, either alone or in conjunction with others.

(2)    Someone can be his own master (sui iuris) but not owner of self (sui dominis) since he is accountable to humanity in his own person (6:270)

[Property] Right is “having”, a type of spatial and temporal relation, as under my control, a predicable or derivative concept in category of causality.

Doctrine of Right defines the rightfully mine (meum iuris) and rightfully yours (tuem iuris)

Two kinds of possession

A Empirical

Sensible

Physical proximity

Analytic fact of holding

No p. property in Nature

Unilateral acquisition, choice

Individual outside of society (perhaps fictional)

B Rightful

Intelligible, noumenal,

rational

Physical presence / contact not necc.

 

Civil Law necessary for p. Property

Omnilateral contract [universal law of freedom]

Social, political, civil

 

A

Positive use

Individual will

Right of person to self. Right of humanity in our own person

Acquisition

 

B

Negative restriction (exclusive)

Will of all; common will

EXTERNAL: Original common Possession of earth is precondition 4 exclusive ownership

Ownership

Right to coerce and refuse coercion

General Kant:

·       All justification requires a public ground (eg categorical imperative, aesthetic judgment)

·       According to Henry Allison and Dieter Henrich, all three of Kant’s critiques are organized according to the common legal distinction between quid facti (fact of acquisition) and quid juris (right to have something).

 

 

HEGEL AND PERSON

 

Hegel continues the genealogy of property and persons

For Hegel, property rights neither derive from specific claims of particular individuals nor emanate from an abstract speculative ideal.  Instead, these rights emerge historically along with the general development of the world spirit and of human subjectivity.  In Philosophy of Right, Hegel seeks the rational historical meaning of the actual institution of property ownership in his contemporary world.

 

      Joachim Ritter draws attention to the historical importance of Hegel's connection between personhood and property.  Hegel transforms Kant's categorical imperative, a command to act according to a maxim that one could accept as a universal law, into a generalized rule for all particular relationships between persons.  "The commandment of right is therefore:  be a person and respect others as persons."  Ritter explains that the term "person" is not merely a generic synonym for an instance of the human species, but has a specific historical valence for Hegel. In Roman Law, the term "person" was used to refer only to a certain type of citizen who had certain types of rights.  "What is called the right of persons in Roman Law, it regards a human being only if he enjoys a certain status." Among his other privileges, a Roman person is permitted to own as property certain unfree individuals, Roman slaves. Hegel's assessment that history has made freedom common among all persons therefore correlates with his analysis of the generality of property rights. 

 

      For Hegel, personhood is the first step in the ethical journey of the discrete individual. Prior to socialization, one must be able to reflect upon one's own unique freedom. Waldron explains, "To be a person is to be a subject preoccupied self-consciously with the freedom of one's will"  That is, a person is an independent individual who (a "who" and not a "that") is capable of having rights and of realizing freedom.  As a capacity for self-possession and for external appropriation, property ownership is the first right of this emergent personhood.  It is the foundation for the rights to life, liberty, and all other possible rights. The historical realization of free personhood for all men therefore entails the assertion of a general property right.  As Waldron "crudely" puts it, "men have a general right to private property because being the owner of something is in some sense constitutive of freedom."

 

      To be free, a will requires property as a way to externalize itself in the world.  Freedom is not an abstract and transcendental quality that remains locked within an internal mental sphere. Instead, it must be actualized in concrete matter.  The mind first possesses its body as the necessary medium for the development of its freedom.   This embodiment of the will allows the person to identify itself as a determinate being that is "free in its own eyes"  Furthermore, the will permeates objects, converting them into property imbued with its labor.  Because the will externalizes itself in such a fashion, objects have a necessary and concrete reference to a particular person's will.  By juxtaposing this notion to Hegel's analysis of the lord and bondsman, Waldron notes that property not only extends the will spatially but also temporally.  He explains, "Laboring on materials imposes some sort of permanence and stability on the projects of the will." (p. 372.)  In this manner, a general right of private property allocates enduring control over concrete things to free persons.

 

      As a counterpoint to the individuated and free character of persons, Hegel posits Nature as an open expanse where man can freely externalize his will and domination. As in Locke, the person’s own labor transforms nature from an alien terrain into a thing that serves his will.  This realm of property functions as a medium through which persons can relate to each other. Hegel asserts, "It is only as owners of property that the two [persons] have existence for each other." Concrete embodiment not only allows the individual to identify himself, but also allows others to recognize him through this external manifestation. When a thing is possessed as personal property, other persons can recognize that this object ultimately refers back to the will of its owner. Private property both demarcates the particular sphere of an individual's rights and duties, and allows social actors to relate to each other in a rightful and dutiful manner.

 

      Property rights enable persons to interact through contracts.  Whereas a person's will is embodied in and referenced through an external object, the will is not totally identified with this object.   Therefore, one can withdraw one's will from a particular property and alienate it to another person.  A contract allows a person to transcend herself through an exchange of external properties that relates her internal will to the will of another.  In addition to alienating material objects, one can also alienate a limited portion of one's labor time while still maintaining one's freedom. 

Whereas external objects may be alienated from a person and even his labor may be alienated for a certain duration, there can never be a right to alienate the entirety of his internal will.  Hegel condemns the Roman institution of slavery for confusing personhood with property.  He indicates that this institution is rooted in the misconception that man is simply a natural entity: one can only appropriate and dominate nature, but other persons have independent wills, freedoms, and rationality.  By trying to treat the slave as something that can be dominated by her will, the master therefore attempts to externalize herself in an inappropriate way

 

 

Marx

               Whereas Locke defines property as that which can be integrated back into a person’s dominion through his bodily labor, Marx argues that, under capitalism, private property emerges as the thing that is alienated from the labor of the proletariat.  “Private property is therefore the product, result, and necessary consequence of alienated labor, of the external relation of the worker to nature and to himself.”

According to Marx, man’s activity is directed towards securing the means of his existence.  Human labor transforms nature into the objects of culture, thereby developing the collective species being of humanity.  “In creating an objective world by his practical activity, man proves himself a conscious species being.” Capitalism, however, transforms this necessary objectification into alienation.  The wage laborer produces neither something that will sustain him nor an object that belongs to him.  Instead, the products of his labor become the private property of another person, the capitalist. 

Contra Locke and Hegel, Marx insists that private property is not an essential factor in human self-manifestation but a particular historical manifestation of capitalist society.  István Mészáros elucidates Marx’s particular conception of private property by distinguishing between first-order and second-order mediations.  He explains that “‘first order mediation’ itself – productive activity as such – is an absolute ontological factor of the human predicament.”  As mentioned above, human labor mediates the natural world by turning it into the objects of culture.  Because this productive activity necessarily occurs within a certain social setting, labor also mediates human relationships with one another.  Whereas this first-order mediation is part of human existence itself, capitalism introduces a second-order mediation by interposing within the dynamic process the commercial triad of exchange, private property, and division of labor.  These capitalistic structures mediate the process of mediation itself, alienating the worker from his ontological connection to objects, to other people, and even to her own identity as an active being.

               For Marx, money is the alienated medium through which use value is alienated into exchange value.  “By possessing the property of buying everything, by possessing the property of appropriating all objects, money is thus the object of eminent possession  … Money is the pimp between man’s need and the object, between his life and his means of life.”  Money thus consummates the reification of capitalism. “The riddle of the money fetish is therefore the riddle of the commodity fetish.”

               The fact that money has become the object of eminent possession indicates the worker’s relation to property ownership.  Marx explains that the worker is compelled to pursue the abstract property of currency because capitalism has expropriated from him all concrete means of production.  A man enters into the world as a laborer only because “he is free of all the objects needed for the realization of his labor-power.”  Not only does he not own the objects of labor, he has little capacity to produce the means of life, the use values, to satisfy his own needs.  Marx stresses that the situation of the worker is not the product of a purely natural state of affairs, but the result of specific historical conditions.  “In order to become a commodity, the product must cease to be produced as the immediate subsistence of the producer himself.”  Whereas the peasant villager can provide for himself, the historical genesis of a capitalist commodity economy has prevented an industrial worker from doing so. 

            Man’s alienation from the means of production alienates him from his status as a person.  Marx defines humans through their activity, calling labor power “the aggregate of those mental and physical capabilities existing in the living form, the living personality, of a human being,”  However, capitalism reifies this activity into a calculable commodity.  “What [the political economists] call the ‘value of labor’ is in fact the value of labor-power as it exists in the personality of the laborer.” Marx thus indicates the degree of alienation by showing how commodity capitalism first converts the human person into a laborer, then views the laborer in terms of her labor-power, then uses her labor-power for labor, and then exploits her labor to extract value.  Marx’s book Capital enacts this transformation by referring to individual laborers and capitalists as “personifications” of abstract categories.   Capitalism transforms the human person into “variable capital” from which surplus value can be extracted. Thus, Marx explains that this work process estranges the worker both spiritually and physically, saying that “manufacture mutilates the worker, turning him into a fragment of himself.” 

               Through his labor, the worker establishes himself as a subject creating a world of external objects, a totality of cultural products.  Under capitalism, the worker experiences this self-objectification as self-estrangement because the fruits of his labor do not belong to him: they are delivered over to an Other, the capitalist.  “If the product of labor does not belong to the worker, this is only possible because it belongs to another man than the worker.” (78) A process of self-mortification, alienated labor converts the living essence of the worker into dead matter, sacrificing him to a stranger.  Work is “vitality as a sacrifice of life, production of the object as loss of the object to an alien power, an alien person ...  who is alien to labor and the worker.” (81) 

 

 

Levinas

 

            For Levinas, the critique of history has always been echoed by a critique of property ownership.  In the opening section Principle and Anarchy of “Substitution,” Levinas explains that in Western ontology, essence fluctuates by losing itself and finding itself out of an archē, allowing it to “possess itself” and to instantiate a “moment of having in being.” (1981, 99)  This doubling of having and being occurs throughout Levinas’s writing.  In his 1935 article against “Hitlerism,” he condemns fascist thought for figuring the body as an inevitable bondage to history.  In contrast, Western thought has spiritually detached man from time and physicality.  He characterizes this as a “power given to the soul to free itself from what has been” (1990b, 66), italicizing the pluperfect combination of to have and to be that grammatically converts the past into a possession. 

            Immediately after World War II, Levinas introduces the notion of an “il y a (there is), the undifferentiated whole of existence that compels part-icipation, possessing and nullifying any private separation.  Not only does this term parody Heidegger’s idea of a generous “es gibt” (idiomatically “there is”; literally “it gives”), it redefines Being as an anonymous it (il) in a there (y) that has (a) existence.  Emerging from this flux as someone who can be requires becoming someone who can have:  the me (moi) that I am doubles as the self (soi) that I own.  Through this hypostasis, the self posits itself in a particular space at a particular moment.  This self-mastery allows the self to convert exteriority into personal property by exerting its labor. 

            Levinas’ economic analyses in Totality and Infinity draw from classical political philosophy.  Like Locke, he defines the act of possession as an appropriation of external being.  One is born into a sensuous element whose arche escapes ownership, something that is “coming always, without my being able to possess the source.”  Labor stills this anonymous flux and postpones the unforeseeable future of Infinity by allowing one to maintain oneself in a present.  It breaks me free of my dependence on the element by suspending its independence.  “Possession neutralizes this being: as property the thing is an existent that has lost his being.”  By generating a total ensemble of things that answer to the needs of a separated ego, ownership thereby establishes the self’s mastery over external reality.

            Levinas inveighs against the ontological tradition for reducing the world to Being and beings that ultimately refer back to ownership.  Despite his insistence that Dasein is not a human person, even Heidegger poses the question of Being as eigenlichtkeit, “own-like-ness” or “authenticity,” and as ereigen, “en-own-ing” or “the event of appropriation.”  Levinas argues: “The relation with Being that is enacted as ontology consists in neutralizing the existent in order to comprehend or grasp it.  It is hence not a relation with the other as such, but the reduction of the other to the same.  ...  a suppression or possession of the other”.

            Although this possession establishes one’s sovereign ownership over otherness, it also indicates “a certain form of economic life” (Levinas 1969, 172) with an Other, a stranger.  Levinas’s analysis of labor combines and generalizes Locke’s understanding of property as integration with Marx’s understanding of it as alienation, “an estrangement of man from man” (Marx 1978, 77).  Labor relates the world to the self by positing entities as graspable objects.  Because these works are positioned within a social ensemble of work, they also relate to the possessive grasp of an Other who presents himself as a Master and property owner.  “The inexpressive character of the product is reflected in its market value, in its suitability for others, in its capability to assume the meaning others will give it, to enter into an entirely different context from that which engendered it.” (Levinas 1969, 227) 

            As in Marx, relationships of exchange disrupt the integrity of personhood.  Not just commercial products, but one’s will and one’s body are alienated in the instant that they are manifested.  The projects a will initiates are always co-opted by another person.  As an owned body, a “corps propre” (229), one positions oneself as a corporeal being, exposing one’s material self to being bought for gold or being murdered by steel.  Therefore, one’s birth into a present moment is experienced as a kind of suicide.  One becomes registered in history through the mortified material products of one’s labor, “the works of dead wills” (228)

            As an act of appropriation, property ownership necessarily proceeds from violence and ultimately from murder.  Levinas’ discussion of the first ethical commandment, You Shall Not Commit Murder, is sometimes misunderstood to be simply an ultimate moral prohibition.  However, Levinas explains, “this interdiction is to be sure not equivalent to pure and simple impossibility, and even presupposes the possibility which precisely it forbids.” (232-3)  Although murder is an ethical impossibility, it is preeminently an event that occurs within every single instant of time.  The Other is always approached and appropriated through a doubling of his origination and his death: through his production in a work, his incarnation in a body, and his representation under a concept.  At every instant, I seize the Other through his manifestation, suspending his existence, and grasping him historically through the records of his past.  This everyday occurrence can be grasped most clearly on the digital commons where, online, one encounters the preservation of moments from different past identities; the real lives of real people reduced to and articulated as a multiplicity of media.

            This murder is enacted at every moment as cannibalism, as consumption of another person’s corpse.  All of Levinas’s analyses of materiality, of need and eating, of the content of elemental jouissance, of the goods encountered in a home, and even of hunger and destitution, must be understood in relation to this vampirism, this flesh-eating. [Also taken from Husserl’s concept of he content “filling” consciousness] Levinas explains, “in satiety the real I sank my teeth into is assimilated, the forces that were in the other become my forces, become me.” The past of the other, his death, has become retrospectively incorporated into my own present moment of consumption.  Therefore, I -- as a consumer, through the things I purchase and use -- become entangled in a net of works, in networks of responsibility.  These responsibilities manifest in consciousness once I understand that the products which result in my enjoyment are ultimately the results of human and environmental degradation and death.

            Taking into account the relationship between death and consumable products, one can deduce that the first ethical commandment, You Shall Not Kill, results in a corollary: You Shall Not Steal.  Levinas explicitly recognizes this relationship between ownership and robbery.  “To approach someone from works is to enter into his interiority by burglary; the other is surprised in his intimacy, where, like the personages of history, he is, to be sure, exposed, but does not express himself.”   As mentioned above, these ethical impossibilities point to everyday realities:  not only does one murder in every moment of consumption, one’s ownership of Property is Theft.